3,410 research outputs found

    The Structure of Blackstone\u27s Commentaries

    Get PDF

    An Approach to Customary Law

    Full text link
    A proper understanding of the nature of customary law is important for legal historians. For students of European legal history, customary law is particularly important; from post-Roman times to the beginning of the modern legal age in the eighteenth century, the two main elements in European law have been Roman law and legal custom. In large measure, the main task of lawyers of that interim time period was to unify or harmonize the two strands of Roman law and custom. Customary law flourishes in circumstances where law is likely to be the least theoretical. Yet, the nature of any source of law requires theoretical underpinnings regardless of whether these underpinnings are always implicit and never expressed. Accordingly, for custom to be regarded as law in Western private law, more than simple usage must be and is required, even if the usage is general and has long flourished. The principle issue is that one cannot derive an ought from an is. Consistent behavior in accordance with particular implicit rules does not indicate that people should so behave, or conversely should be subject to some sanction if they do not. The main problem for any theory of customary law seems to be determining the nature of the additional factor required to transform custom into law. The Roman sources clearly indicate that some additional factor is needed to recognize custom as law, even if the nature of this factor is not apparent. For example, the Epitome Ulpiani states that [c]ustom is the tacit consent of the people, deeply rooted through long usage. The additional factor is expressed by the otherwise tautological tacit consent or tacit agreement (tacitus consensus). But, this approach raises the question as to what has tacit consent been given? Certainly, tacit consent is not given to the long usage itself, although the tacit consent is rooted in the long usage. Another Roman source, the Justiniani Institutiones, states that [u]nwritten law is that which usage has approved. For long-practiced customs, endorsed by the consent of the users, take on the appearance of statute. In this instance, the additional factor is expressed by endorsed by the consent of the users (consenu utentium comprobati). Nevertheless, the vagueness of Ulpian is not dissipated as a result of this other explanation. The Justiniani Digesta, however, clarifies the nature of the additional factor by stating that [d]eeply rooted custom is observed as a statute, not undeservedly; and this is what is called law established by usage. For since statutes themselves bind us for no other reason than because they have been accepted by the judgment of the people, then deservedly those things which the people have approved without writing will bind all. For what does it matter that the people declare its wish by vote or by positive acts and conduct? Therefore, it is very rightly accepted that laws are abrogated not only by the vote of him who proposes law, but also through desuetude, by the tacit consent of all. For Julian, the nature of the additional factor seems to be clearer: apparently the custom is law because the people accept it as law. This article discusses the dominant theory which legal historians have adopted to explain how custom is transformed into law: opinio necessitatis. Although legal historians generally accept the doctrine, it has a number of theoretical failings which hamper its usefulness as an explanatory tool. Accordingly, this article analyzes those failings and an alternate theory that custom becomes law only when it is the subject of statute or judicial decision. Finally, the article proposes nine propositions related to the role of judgments in creating customary law

    Seventeenth-Century Jurists, Roman Law, and the Law of Slavery - Symposium on the Law of Slavery: Comparative Law and Slavery

    Get PDF

    Tignum Iunctum: The XII Tables and a Lost Word

    Full text link
    A text of the scholar Festus, which is famous among Latinists and lawyers alike, reads: Tignum non solum in aedificiis, quo utuntur, appellatur, sed etiam in vineis, ut est in XII: Tignum iunctum aedibus vineave et concapit ne solvito . For the quotation from the XII Tables, the manuscripts showsome variation for \u27vineave\u27: \u27victum\u27 in W, \u27vineaque\u27 in V and \u27minerve\u27 in X. But these we can happily leave aside and com to the crux of the text, \u27concapit\u27, which appears in all the manuscripts. \u27Concapit\u27, a corrupt word, and difficult of explanation say Lewis and Short! And the emendations proposed are numerous and lacking in general approval. J.J. Scaliger suggested \u27e concapi\u27, Cuiacius \u27et concapit\u27, Mommsen \u27e compage\u27, Gotz \u27e concapidine\u27, Muller \u27e concapte\u27, but Schoell reverts to \u27e concapi\u27 and Huschke has \u27sei concapit\u27. Riccobono excises the words altogether. To show that the age of invention is not over I wish to propose and defend yet another emendation which will have its own particular virtues, legal and linguistic

    Roman Slave Law: An Anglo-American Perspective

    Full text link
    When one looks at Roman slave law from an Anglo-American perspective, what is striking is the apparent disinterest or lack of concern in the subject on the part of the state and the corresponding freedom of action allowed to slave owners. My claim is not that there was little law--indeed there was a great deal--but that the state did not get overly involved in laying down what owners could do with their slaves. For instance, though law decreed the methods by which slaves could be freed, the state imposed very few restrictions on manumission. This is all the more striking in that manumission gave citizenship as well as freedom. Roman citizenship was highly prized, giving economic advantages as well as status
    • …
    corecore